ethics-of-care

Ethics of care is a feminist approach to ethics. It challenges traditional moral theories as male centric and problematic to the extent they omit or downplay values and virtues usually culturally associated with women or with roles that are often cast as ‘feminine’.

The best example of this may be seen in how ethics of care differs from two dominant normative moral theories of the 18thand 19thcentury. The first is deontology, best associated with Immanuel Kant. And the second utilitarianism, attributed to Jeremy Bentham and improved upon by John Stuart Mill.

They each require the moral agent to be unemotional. Moral decision making is thus expected to be rational and logical, with a focus on universal, objective rules. In contrast, ethics of care defends some emotions, such as care or compassion, as moral.

On this view, there is not a dichotomy between reason and the emotions – as some emotions may be reasonable and morally appropriate in guiding good decisions or actions. Feminist ethics also recognises that rules must be applied in a context, and real life moral decision making is influenced by the relationships we have with those around us.

Instead of asking the moral decision maker to be unbiased, the caring moral agent will consider that one’s duty may be greater to those they have particular bonds with, or to others who are powerless rather than powerful.

 

 

In a Different Voice

Traditional proponents of feminist care ethics include 20thcentury theorists Carol Gilligan (b. 1936) and Nel Noddings (b. 1929). Gilligan’s influential 1982 book, In a Different Voice, claimed that Sigmund Freud’s theory of psychoanalysis and Lawrence Kohlberg’s theory of moral development were biased and male oriented.

On these dominant psychological accounts of human development, male development is taken as standard, and female development is often judged as inferior in various ways.

Gilligan argued if women are ‘more emotional’ than men, and pay more attention to relationships rather than rules, this is not a sign of their being less ethical, but, rather, of different values, that are equally valuable. While Gilligan may have deemed these differences to be ‘natural’ and associated with sex rather than gender, these differences may well have been socially constructed and therefore the result of ‘nurture’.

How might the ethics of care theorist resolve the classical ‘Heinz’ dilemma: should a moral agent steal the required medicine he cannot afford to buy to give to his very sick wife, or stick to the rule ‘do not steal’, regardless of the circumstances? A tricky dilemma to be sure as there are competing duties here (namely, a positive duty to help those in need as well as a negative duty to avoid stealing).

Arguably, the caring person would place the relationship with one’s spouse above any relationship they may or may not have with the pharmacist, and care or compassion or love would outweigh a rule (or a law) in this case, leading to the conclusion that the right thing to do is to steal the medicine.

Note: the utilitarian may also claim a moral agent should steal the medicine because saving the wife’s life is a better outcome than whatever negative consequences may result from stealing. However, the reasoning that leads to this conclusion is based on unemotional weighing of costs and benefits, rather than a consideration of the relationships involved and asking what love might demand.

Writing at the same time as Gilligan, Noddings also defended care as a particular form of moral relationship. She sees children as naturally caring (with the exception of sociopaths and psychopaths) and claims this is a prerequisite for ethical caring. While Noddings does not rule men out from being caring, it is usually women who feature in her examples of caregivers. Noddings, like Gilligan, prioritises relationships that are between specific individuals in a particular context as the basis for ethical behaviour. This stands in contrast to the idea that morality involves following a universal, abstract moral rule.

Who cares? 

Ethics of care has been influential in areas such as education, counselling, nursing and medicine. Yet there have also been feminist criticisms. Some worry that linking women to the trait of caring maintains a sexist stereotype and encourages women to continue to nurture others, to their own detriment, and even while society fails to value carers as they ought. While Noddings claims moral agents also need to care for themselves, this is so they are better able to continue caring for others.

Obviously, it is not only women who care or who take on caregiving roles (paid or unpaid). Yet empathetic professions such as nursing, teaching, childcare, and counselling are female dominated, and women still do the majority of unpaid caring roles including childrearing and domestic duties in the home.

So let’s hear it for the carers, and support policies that seek fair remuneration, equal respect and value for those in caregiving roles.

Join the conversation

Who would you do wrong for to do right by?